Page 9«..78910

Category Archives: Ethical Egoism

Ethical Egoism and Biblical Self-Interest | Papers at …

Posted: June 27, 2016 at 6:24 am

Illogic Primer Quotes Clippings Books and Bibliography Paper Trails Links Film

J.P. Moreland, Westminster Theological Journal 59 (1997), pp. 257-68. Nov 30 . 1997

The Old and New Testaments contain a number of passages that in some way or another associate moral obligation with self-interest in the form of seeking rewards and avoiding punishment. Thus, Exod 20:12 says Honor your father and your mother, that your days may be prolonged in the land which the Lord your God gives you. Jesus tells us to seek first His kingdom, and His righteousness; and all these things shall be added to you (Matt 6:33). On another occasion he warns his listeners that at the end of the age the angels shall come forth, and take out the wicked from among the righteous, and will cast them into the furnace of fire; there shall be weeping and gnashing of teeth (Matt 13:49-50). Paul states his ambition to be pleasing to the Lord for we must all appear before the judgment-seat of Christ, that each one may be recompensed for his deeds. (II Cor 5:10). The fact that rewards and punishments are associated with self-interest and moral or religious obligation is clear throughout the scriptures. What is not so clear is just how to understand these passages from the point of view of normative moral theory. More specifically, do texts of this sort imply that ethical egoism (to be defined below) is the correct normative ethical theory derived from the Bible? In over a decade of teaching ethics, I regularly have students, when first exposed to ethical egoism, draw the conclusion that this ethical system is, indeed, the best way to capture biblical ethics. And while popular works on the spiritual life are not sophisticated enough to be clear on the matter, a number of them, especially those that promote a prosperity gospel, would seem to be expressions of ethical egoism.

The identification of ethical egoism with biblical ethics is not confined to popular venues. Secular philosopher John Hospers argues that when believers justify being moral on the basis of a doctrine of eternal rewards and punishments, this is simply an appeal to self-interest . [N]othing could be a clearer appeal to naked and unbridled power than this.1 The vast majority of Christian philosophers and theologians have seen some combination of deontological and virtue ethics to be the best way to capture the letter and spirit of biblical ethics. Still, the problem of egoism has been noted by some and embraced by others. Years ago, Paul Ramsey raised the problem of ethical egoism when he queried,

But what of salvation? Is not salvation the end for which Christians quest? What of rewards in the kingdom of heaven? What of mans everlasting and supernatural good, the souls life with God in the hereafter mans chief end, glorifying God and enjoying him forever. Is not salvation itself a supreme value which Christians seek with earnest passion, each first of all for himself?2

Theologian Edward John Carnell (inaccurately in my view) has been understood as having promoted some form of ethical egoism.3

In recent years, Christian philosopher and theologian Philip R. West has argued that deontological ethics do not capture biblical morality and that ethical egoism is the correct normative theory in this regard. Says West, They [the OT writers] apparently believed not only that actual divine punishment is enough to establish the obligation to obey divine commands, but like Paul, that the absence of actual divine punishment erodes the obligatory status of these commands.4 Elsewhere, West defends the thesis that some agent A has a moral obligation to do P if and only if doing P will maximize As own self-interest. He argues that since scripture grounds our obligations in self-interest (rewards/punishments), this amounts to ethical egoism.

What should we make of this claim? Is ethical egoism the correct normative theory from a biblical point of view? My purpose in what follows is to show why ethical egoism is a defective normative ethical theory and, given this conclusion, to offer ways to understand biblical self-interest that do not entail the truth of ethical egoism. In what follows, I will, first, clarify the precise nature of ethical egoism; second, summarize the main types of arguments for and against ethical egoism in the literature and conclude that ethical egoism is inadequate; third, offer a set of distinctions for understanding biblical self-interest while avoiding ethical egoism.

The most plausible form of ethical egoism, embraced by philosophers such as Ayn Rand and John Hospers, is called universal or impersonal rule-egoism (hereafter, simply ethical egoism). Since Hospers is the most prominent philosopher to advocate ethical egoism, his definition is the most pertinent: each person has a moral duty to follow those moral rules that will be in the agents maximal self-interest over the long haul.5 For the ethical egoist, one has a duty to follow correct moral rules. And the factor that makes a rule a correct one is that, if followed, it will be in the agents own best interests in the long run. Each person ought to advance his own self-interests and that is the sole foundation of morality.

Ethical egoism is sometimes confused and identified with various distinct issues. First, there is individual or personal ethical egoism which says everyone has a duty to act so as to serve my self-interests. Here, everyone is morally obligated to serve the speakers long term best interests. Second, there is psychological egoism, roughly, the idea that each person can only do that act which the person takes to maximize his or her own self-interest. Psychological egoism is a descriptive thesis about motivation to the effect that we can only act on motives that are in our own self-interests. As we shall see shortly, psychological egoism is sometimes used as part of an argument for ethical egoism, but the two are distinct theses.

Third, ethical egoism is not the same thing as egotism an irritating character trait of always trying to be the center of attention. Nor is it the same as what is sometimes called being a wanton. A wanton has no sense of duty at all, but only acts to satisfy his or her own desires. The only conflict the wanton knows is that between two or more desires he cannot simultaneously satisfy (e.g. to eat more and lose weight). The wanton knows nothing about duty. Arguably, animals are wantons. Fifth, ethical egoism is not to be confused with being an egoist, i.e. being someone who believes that the sole worth of an act is its fairly immediate benefits to the individual himself. With this understanding of ethical egoism as a backdrop, let us look at the arguments for and against ethical egoism that have been preeminent in the literature. A detailed treatment of these arguments is not possible here, but by looking briefly at the main considerations usually brought to bear on ethical egoism, a feel for its strengths and weaknesses as a normative ethical theory emerges.

Among the arguments for ethical egoism, two have distinguished themselves, at least in textbook treatments of the position.6 First, it is argued that ethical egoism follows from psychological egoism in this way: psychological egoism is true and this implies that we always and cannot help but act egoistically. This is a fact about human motivation and action. Further, ought implies can. If I ought to do x, if I have a duty to do x, then I must be able to do x. If I cannot do something, then I have no duty or responsibility to do it. Applied to egoism, this means that since I can act egoistically, then I have a duty to do so and since I cannot act non-egoistically, then I have no duty to do so. Thus, ethical egoism is the correct picture of moral obligation in keeping with what we know about human motivation.

Does this argument work? Most philosophers have not thought so. First, the principle of psychological egoism, viz. that we always act to maximize our own self-interest, is ambiguous. So stated, the principle falls to make a distinction between the result of an act vs. the intent of an act. If it is understood in the former way it is irrelevant and if taken in the latter way it is false. If the statement merely asserts that, as a matter of fact, the result of our actions is the maximization of self-interest, then this does not imply ethical egoism. Ethical egoism is the view that the thing which morally justifies an act is the agents intent to maximize his own self-interests. So the mere psychological fact (if it is a fact) that people only do those acts that result in their own satisfaction proves nothing.

On the other hand, if the statement claims that we always act solely with the intent to satisfy our own desires, then this claim is simply false. Every day we are aware of doing acts with the sole intent of helping someone else, of doing something just because we think it is the right thing to do, and of expressing virtuous, other-centered behavior. As Christian phiosopher Joseph Butler (1692-1752) argued:

Mankind has various instincts and principles of action as brute creatures have; Some leading most directly and immediately to the good of the community, and some most directly to private good [I]t is not a true representation of mankind, to affirm that they are wholly governed by self-love, the love of power and sensual appetites . it is manifest fact, that the same persons, the generality, are frequently influenced by friendship, compassion, gratitude; and liking of what is fair and just, takes its turn amongst the other motives of action.7

Furthermore, it is not even true that we always try to do what we want or what we think is in our self-interests. We sometimes experience akrasia (weakness of will) when we fail to do or even try to do what we want (see Rom 7:15-25). And we sometimes do (or try to do) our duty even when we dont want to do it. These points appear to be facts about human action.

Second, this argument for ethical egoism suffers from what has been called the paradox of hedonism. Often, the best way maximize self-interest, say, to get happiness and the satisfaction of desire is not to aim at it. Happiness is not usually achieved as an intended goal, but rather, it is a bi-product of a life well lived and of doing what is right. If people always act in order to gain happiness, then it will remain forever elusive. Thus, psychological egoism contains a paradox when viewed as a model of human intention and action.

Finally, as a model of human action, psychological egoism rules out the possibility of libertarian freedom of the will. Briefly put, it should be noted that if libertarian freedom of the will is the correct view of human action, then the following implications follow: 1) no amount of internal states (e.g. desires, beliefs, emotions) are sufficient to produce behavior, and 2) the agent himself must spontaneously exercise his causal powers and act for the sake of reasons which function as teleological goals. For libertarians, a free act is never determined by any particular reason, including desire. Thus, on this view, psychological egoism is false if taken as a total account of human action because it implies that a person must always act for a self-interested reason. Libertarian freedom is controversial and not everyone accepts this model of human action. But the point is that for those who do, it counts as a counter-argument to psychological egoism.

A second argument for ethical egoism is called the closet utilitarian position. Some point out that if everyone acted in keeping with ethical egoism, the result would be the maximization of happiness for the greatest number of people. If acted upon, ethical egoism, as a matter of fact, leads to the betterment of humanity. There are two main problems with this argument. First, it amounts to a utilitarian justification of ethical egoism. Utilitarianism is a normative ethical theory to the effect that a moral action or rule is correct if and only if performing that act or following that rule maximizes the greatest amount of non-moral good vs. bad for the greatest number compared to alternative acts or rules open to the agent. While both are consequentialist in orientation, nevertheless, utilitarianism and ethical egoism are rival normative theories. It is inconsistent, therefore, for someone to use a rival theory, in this case, utilitarianism, as the moral justification for ethical egoism. If one is an ethical egoist, why should he or she care about the greatest good for the greatest number for its own sake, and not merely because such caring would itself lead to greater satisfaction of ones individual desires? Second, the claim seems to be factually false. Is it really the case that if everyone acted according to ethical egoism, it would maximize everyones happiness? Surely not. Sometimes self-sacrifice is needed to maximize happiness for the greatest number, and this argument for ethical egoism cannot allow for personal denial.

There are other arguments for ethical egoism, but these two have been the most central for those who advocate this normative theory. As we have seen, both arguments fail. By contrast, the main arguments against ethical egoism seem to be strong enough to justify rejecting the system as an adequate normative theory.

Among the arguments against ethical egoism, three are most prominent. First, is the publicity objection. Moral principles must serve as action guides that inform moral situations. Most moral situations involve more than one person and, in this sense, are public situations. Thus, moral action guides must be teachable to others so they can be publically used principles that help us in our interpersonal moral interactions. However, according to ethical egoism itself, there is a possible world where it is immoral for me to teach others to embrace ethical egoism because that could easily turn out not to be in my own self-interest. It may be better for me if others always acted altruistically. Thus, it could be immoral for one to go public and teach ethical egoism to others and, if so, this would violate one of the necessary conditions for a moral theory, namely, that it be teachable to others.

Philosopher Fred Feldman has offered a rejoinder to this argument.8 He claims that we have no good reason to believe that a moral doctrine needs to be consistently promulgatable. Why, he asks, should we have to be able to teach a moral doctrine to others? Someone could consistently hold to the following moral notion P as a part of his overall moral system: it is never right to promulgate anything. Unfortunately, this response fails because it does not capture the public nature of moral principles (or normative ethical theories) in so far as they serve as action guides to adjudicate interpersonal moral conflict. How could the principle it is never right to promulgate anything serve as an action guide sufficient to deal with the various aspects of duty, virtue, and rights that constitute much of the point of action guides in the first place?

Moreover, this response fails to take into account the universalizability of moral rules. If I should never promulgate anything, then this implies that I should not teach something to someone else. But there does not seem to be a clear moral difference in this case between others and myself. To be consistent, then, I should not proclaim this moral principle to myself. Perhaps I should try to hide from myself the fact that I accept this role. This implies, among other things, that if I hold to P as a moral principle that should be universalized, then, applying P to myself, I would no longer have moral grounds for continuing to embrace P on the basis of reasons known to me or for making P known to myself. I should do my best to forget P or talk myself out of believing P. On the other hand, if I do not think P should be universalized, then in what sense is P a moral principle (since universalizability is most likely a necessary condition for a principle counting as moral)?

A second argument against ethical egoism is called the paradox of egoism. Some things, e.g. altruism, deep love, genuine friendship, are inconsistent with ethical egoism. Why? Because these features of a virtuous, moral life require us not to seek our own interests but, rather, those of others. Moreover, ethical egoism would seem to imply that helping others at ones own expense (and other acts of self sacrifice) is wrong if it is not in my long term self-interest to do so. Thus, egoism would seem to rule out important, central features of the moral life. The main point of a normative moral theory is to explain and not to eliminate what we already know to be central facets of morality prior to ethical theorizing. Furthermore, in order to reach the goal of egoism (e.g., personal happiness), one must give up egoism and be altruistic in love, friendship, and other ways. Thus, egoism is paradoxical in its own right and it eliminates key aspects of the moral life.

Some respond by claiming that altruism is fully consistent with ethical egoism. Hospers argues that, according to ethical egoism, we ought to do acts that benefit others because that is in our own self-interests.9 In a similar vein, Fred Feldman asserts that egoism allows us to perform altruistic actions provided that such actions are ultimately in our own self-interests.10 But this response fails to distinguish pseudo-altruism from genuine altruism.

Genuine altruism requires that an altruistic act have, as its sole, or at least main intent, the benefit of the other. An act whose sole or ultimate intent is self-interest but which, nevertheless, does result in the benefit of others is not genuine altruism. If you found out that someone loved you or acted altruistically toward you solely or ultimately with the intent of benefiting himself, then you would not count that as genuine love or altruism even if the act happened to benefit you in some way. Thus, egoistic altruism is a contradiction in terms. Ethical egoism is consistent with pseudo-altruism but not with genuine altruism.

Finally, a third objection claims that ethical egoism leads to inconsistent outcomes. A moral theory must allow for moral rules that are public and universalizable. But ethical egoism could lead to situations where this is not the case. How? Consider two persons A and B in a situation where they have a conflict of interest. For example, suppose there was only one kidney available for transplant, that A and B both need it, and that A or B will die without the transplant. According to universal ethical egoism, A ought to act in his own self-interests and prescribe that his desires come out on top. A had a duty to secure the kidney and thwart Bs attempts to do the same. This would seem to imply that A should prescribe that B has a duty to act in As self-interest. Of course B, according to universal ethical egoism, has from his perspective a duty to act in his own self-interest. But now a contradiction arises because ethical egoism implies that B both has a duty to give the kidney to A and obtain it himself.

Jesse Kalin has responded to this argument by claiming that, as an ethical egoist, A should not hold that B should act in As self-interest, but in Bs own self- interest.11 This would seem to solve the problem of contradictory duty above by rejecting individual ethical egoism (everyone should act in my self-interest) in favor of the universal version (everyone should act in his own self-interest). But this way of stating ethical egoism does not seem to capture the egoistic spirit of the ethical egoism because it leaves open the question as to why egoist A would need to hold that B should act in Bs interests and not in As. In other words, it may not be in As own self-interests to hold to universal, as opposed to individual ethical egoism.

Moreover, there is still a problem for this formulation of ethical egoism which can be brought out as follows: A holds that B has a duty to obtain the kidney for himself, have his interests come out on top, and, thus, harm A. But in this case, ethical egoism still seems to imply an inconsistent posture on As (and Bs) part, namely, that A thinks that B has a duty to get the kidney and harm A but that A has a duty to thwart B. Any moral theory that implies that someone has a moral duty to keep others from doing their moral duty is surely in trouble, so the objection goes. And it is hard to see how an ethical egoist A could claim that someone else had a duty to harm A himself.

Not everyone accepts this argument. Following Kalin, Louis Pojman claims that we often find it to be the case that we have a duty to thwart what is the duty of others, e.g., in a war one soldier has a duty to thwart anothers efforts to do his duty to win. In a case like this, soldiers on different sides do not believe that the other side has adequate moral grounds for being at war.12 If we separate beliefs about ethical situations from desires, so the response goes, then one person can believe the other had a duty to win the war or get the kidney, but the person can also desire to these objectives for himself and act on those desires. In general, the belief that B ought to do x does not imply that A wants B to do x.

What should we make of this response? First, the soldier example fails because it does not distinguish between subjective and objective duty. Subjective duty is one someone has when he has done his best to discover what is and is not the right thing to do. If someone sincerely and conscientiously tries to ascertain what is right, and acts on this, then he has fulfilled his subjective duty and, in a sense, is praiseworthy. But people can be sincerely wrong and fail to live up to their objective duty-the truly correct thing to do from Gods perspective, the overriding moral obligation when all things, including prima facie duties, have been taken into account-even if they have tried to do their best. Admittedly, it is not always easy to determine what the correct objective duty is in a given case. But this is merely an epistemological point and, while valid, it does not negate the legitimacy of the distinction between subjective and objective duty.

Applied to the question at hand, soldier A could only claim that soldier B has both a prima facie duty and a subjective duty to obey his country. But A could also believe that B has an objective duty to do so only if Bs country is, in fact, conducting a morally justified war. Now either A or B is on the right side of the war even though it may be hard to tell which side is correct. Thus, A and B could believe that only one of them actually has an objective duty to fight and thwart the other. So the war example does not give a genuine case where A believes B has a (objective) duty to fight and that he has to thwart B.

Second, what should we make of the claim that we should separate our beliefs about anothers duty from the desire to see that duty done? For one thing, a main point of a moral theory is to describe what a virtuous person is and how we can become such persons. Now, one aspect of a virtuous person is that there is a harmony and unity between desire and duty. A virtuous person desires that the objective moral right be done. Such a person is committed to the good and the right. With this in mind, it becomes clear that ethical egoism, if consistently practiced, could produce fragmented, non-virtuous individuals who believe one thing about duty (e.g., A believes B ought to do x) but who desire something else altogether (e.g., A does not desire B to do x).

However, if we grant that the ethical egoists distinction between beliefs and desires is legitimate from a moral point of view, then this distinction does resolve the claim that ethical egoism leads to a conflict of desire, e.g., A desires the kidney and that B obtain the kidney, since it implies that A believes that B has a duty to receive the kidney but only desires that he himself have it. Nevertheless, this misses the real point of the objection to ethical egoism, namely, that ethical egoism straightforwardly leads to a conflict of desire. Rather, the objection shows that ethical egoism leads to an unresolvable conflict of moral beliefs and moral duty. If A and B are ethical egoists, then A believes that it is wrong for B to have the kidney but also that it is Bs duty to try to obtain it. But how can A consistently believe that B has a duty to do something wrong? And how can A have an objective duty to thwart Bs objective duty?

It would seem, then, that ethical egoism should be rejected as a normative ethical theory and that legitimate self-interest is part of Biblical teaching, e.g. in the passages relating moral obligation to rewards and punishments. If we should not understand these texts as implicitly affirming ethical egoism, how should we understand the self-interest they apparently advocate? I do not think that exegesis alone can solve this problem because the context and grammar of the passages are usually not precise enough to settle the philosophical issue before us. However, if we assume with the majority of thinkers that deontological and virtue ethics, and not ethical egoism, are the correct normative theories implied by Scripture, then we have a set of distinctions that provide a number of legitimate ways of understanding biblical self-interest.

To begin with, we need to distinguish between self-benefit as a bi-product of an act vs. self-interest as the sole intent of an act. Scriptural passages that use self-interest may simply be pointing out that if you intentionally do the right thing, then a good bi-product of this will be rewards of various kinds. It could be argued against philosopher Philip R. West (mentioned earlier) that these passages do not clearly use self-interest as the sole legitimate intent of a moral action.

This observation relates to a second distinction between a motive and a reason. Put roughly, a motive is some state within a person that influences and moves him to action. By contrast, a reason is something that serves to justify rationally some belief that one has or some action one does; a reason for believing or doing x is an attempt to cite something that makes it likely that x be true or that x should be done. In this context, just because something, say self-interest, serves as a motive for an action, it does not follow that it also serves as the reason which justifies the action in the first place. Self-interest may be a legitimate motive for moral action, but, it could be argued, Gods commands, the objective moral law, etc. could be rationally cited as the things that make an act our duty in the first place. The Bible may be citing selfinterest as a motive for action and not as the reason for what makes the act our duty.

Moreover, even if Scripture is teaching that self-interest is a reason for doing some duty, it may be offering self-interest as a prudential and not a moral reason for doing the duty. In other words, the Bible may be saying that it is wise, reasonable, and a matter of good judgment to avoid hell and seek rewards without claiming that these considerations are moral reasons for acting according to self-interest.13 In sum, it could be argued that Scripture can be understood as advocating self-interest as a bi-product and not an intent for action, as a motive and not a reason, or as a prudential and not a moral reason. If this is so, then these scriptural ideas do not entail ethical egoism.

Second, even if scripture teaches that self-interest contributes to making something my moral duty, ethical egoism still does not follow. For one thing, ethical egoism teaches that an act is moral if and only if it maximizes my own self-interests. Ethical egoism teaches that self-interest is both necessary and sufficient for something to be my duty. However, it could be argued that egoistic factors, while not alone morally relevant to an act (other things like self-sacrifice or obeying God for its own sake are relevant as well), nevertheless, are at least one feature often important for assessing the moral worth of an act. Moral duty is not exhausted by self-interest as ethical egoism implies, but self-interest can be a legitimate factor in moral deliberation and scripture may be expressing this point.

Additionally, it is likely that the precise nature of self-interest contained in scripture is different in two ways from that which forms part of ethical egoism. For one thing, according to ethical egoism, the thing that makes an act right is that it is in my self-interest. The important value-making property here is the fact that something promotes the first person interests of the actor. Here, the moral agent attends to himself precisely as being identical to himself and to no one else.

By contrast, the scriptural emphasis on self-interest most likely grounds the appropriateness of such interest, not in the mere fact that these interests are mine, but in the fact that I am a creature of intrinsic value made in Gods image and, as such, ought to care about what happens to me. Here I seek my own welfare not because it is my own, but because of what I am, viz. a creature with high intrinsic value. Consider a possible world where human persons have no value whatever (or where human counter-parts with no intrinsic value exist). In that world, ethical egoism would still legislate self-interest, but the second view under consideration (that self-interest follows from the fact that I am a creature of value) would not because the necessary condition for self-interest (being a creature of intrinsic value) does not obtain in that world.

There is a second way that the nature of self-interest in Scripture and in ethical egoism differ. As C. S. Lewis and C. Stephen Evans have argued, there are different kinds of rewards, and some are proper because they have a natural, intrinsic connection with the things we do to earn them and because they are expressions of what God made us to be by nature. 14 In such cases, these rewards provide a reason to do an activity which does not despoil the character of the activity itself. Money is not a natural reward for love (one is mercenary to marry for money) because money is foreign to the desires that ought to accompany love. By contrast, victory is a natural reward for battle. It is a proper reward because it is not tacked onto the activity for which the reward is given, but rather victory is the consummation of and intrinsically related to the activity itself.

According to Lewis, the desire for heaven and rewards is a natural desire expressing what we, by nature, are. We were made to desire honor before God, to be in his presence, and to hunger to enjoy the rewards he will offer us and these things are the natural consummations of our activity on earth. Thus, the appropriateness of seeking heaven and rewards derives from the fact that these results are genuine expressions of our natures and are the natural consummation of our activities for God. By contrast, according to ethical egoism, the value of results has nothing to do with our natures or with natural consummations of activities. Rather, the worth of those outcomes is solely a function of the fact that they benefit the agent himself.

In sum, self-interest is part of biblical teaching, especially in association with rewards and punishments. But ethical egoism neither captures adequately the nature of biblical self-interest nor is it the best normative ethical theory in its own right. As Christians, we should include self-interest as an important part of our moral and religious lives but without advocating ethical egoism in the process.

With degrees in philosophy, theology and chemisty, Dr. Moreland brings erudition, passion, and his distinctive ebullience to the end of loving God with all of one's mind. Moreland received his B.S. in Chemistry (with honors) from the University of Missouri, his M.A. in Philosophy (with highest honors) from the University of California, Riverside, his Th.M. in Theology (with honors) from Dallas Theological Seminary and his Ph.D. in Philosophy from the University of Southern California. Dr. Moreland has taught theology and philosophy at several schools throughout the U.S. He is currently Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at Biola University's Talbot School of Theology.

Read the rest here:

Ethical Egoism and Biblical Self-Interest | Papers at ...

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ethical Egoism and Biblical Self-Interest | Papers at …

Psychological Egoism vs Ethical Egoism | Flow Psychology

Posted: at 6:24 am

It is said that selfishness is a human nature. Consequently, selfishness is something that relates to egoism. Selfishness is in many forms, which will be discussed later on. Both of these subjects have been a center of discussion for years now. Among the subjects that have been part of it is the topic about psychological egoism vs. ethical egoism.

As for the psychological egoism vs. ethical egoism, the latter is described as the belief in which it states that humans are usually always selfish. Humans are always acting out of their own self-interest, which leads to happiness. The former, however, is the belief that humans are supposed to act only concerning their own interest.

Based on the beliefs itself and how each was defined, the kinds of egoisms that people practice are now differentiated. One type of egoism tells about acting based on or with the presence of a motive and the other acting on something based purely for the persons benefit.

In psychological egoism, it is explained that individuals only do good things because it is in their own interest to do so. As an example, a person decided and chose not to steal for the fact that he or she is afraid to feel the guilt or afraid to go to prison. As for ethical egoism, it is explained that it is just right for individuals to act based on their own self-interest. It means a person acts out for his or her benefit only.

In general, it is described as the empirical doctrine in which the motive for which a person makes a voluntary action is one that falls for that same individuals benefit. In a wider scope, in every action that a person does, even though it is seen as something that is for the benefit of others, there is still a hidden motive that serves for the self-interest of the person.

There are two arguments under this. One, this egoism is considered as a descriptive theory that resulted from the observations made on human behavior. Thus, it can only become a real empirical theory once there are no present exceptions. Second, there is no claim as to how a person should act. Thus, it is a fact that all individuals are seeking their self-interest in the theory. For psychological egoist, they view this as a verifiable and non-moral.

It is described as that doctrine that is prescriptive or normative. It means a person is supposed to seek something only for his own welfare. The primary idea in this belief is that only the persons own welfare is the one valuable for that same individual. There are also two arguments here. One, not all people are naturally seeking just their self-interest. It only claims that people should seek ones self-interest even if not everyone will do the same thing. The second, if it is to be regarded as one theory, then it must be applicable to all persons.

In the end, there is only one thing that can be concluded about the subject psychological egoism vs. ethical egoism. It is that even with the stated theories on egoism, people are not always motivated to act based on selfishness. At times, people just act based on pure kindness in mind.

Dec 20, 2013-Flow Psychology Editor

Read the rest here:

Psychological Egoism vs Ethical Egoism | Flow Psychology

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Psychological Egoism vs Ethical Egoism | Flow Psychology

Ethical Egoism and Biblical Self-Interest | Papers at …

Posted: June 26, 2016 at 10:51 am

Illogic Primer Quotes Clippings Books and Bibliography Paper Trails Links Film

J.P. Moreland, Westminster Theological Journal 59 (1997), pp. 257-68. Nov 30 . 1997

The Old and New Testaments contain a number of passages that in some way or another associate moral obligation with self-interest in the form of seeking rewards and avoiding punishment. Thus, Exod 20:12 says Honor your father and your mother, that your days may be prolonged in the land which the Lord your God gives you. Jesus tells us to seek first His kingdom, and His righteousness; and all these things shall be added to you (Matt 6:33). On another occasion he warns his listeners that at the end of the age the angels shall come forth, and take out the wicked from among the righteous, and will cast them into the furnace of fire; there shall be weeping and gnashing of teeth (Matt 13:49-50). Paul states his ambition to be pleasing to the Lord for we must all appear before the judgment-seat of Christ, that each one may be recompensed for his deeds. (II Cor 5:10). The fact that rewards and punishments are associated with self-interest and moral or religious obligation is clear throughout the scriptures. What is not so clear is just how to understand these passages from the point of view of normative moral theory. More specifically, do texts of this sort imply that ethical egoism (to be defined below) is the correct normative ethical theory derived from the Bible? In over a decade of teaching ethics, I regularly have students, when first exposed to ethical egoism, draw the conclusion that this ethical system is, indeed, the best way to capture biblical ethics. And while popular works on the spiritual life are not sophisticated enough to be clear on the matter, a number of them, especially those that promote a prosperity gospel, would seem to be expressions of ethical egoism.

The identification of ethical egoism with biblical ethics is not confined to popular venues. Secular philosopher John Hospers argues that when believers justify being moral on the basis of a doctrine of eternal rewards and punishments, this is simply an appeal to self-interest . [N]othing could be a clearer appeal to naked and unbridled power than this.1 The vast majority of Christian philosophers and theologians have seen some combination of deontological and virtue ethics to be the best way to capture the letter and spirit of biblical ethics. Still, the problem of egoism has been noted by some and embraced by others. Years ago, Paul Ramsey raised the problem of ethical egoism when he queried,

But what of salvation? Is not salvation the end for which Christians quest? What of rewards in the kingdom of heaven? What of mans everlasting and supernatural good, the souls life with God in the hereafter mans chief end, glorifying God and enjoying him forever. Is not salvation itself a supreme value which Christians seek with earnest passion, each first of all for himself?2

Theologian Edward John Carnell (inaccurately in my view) has been understood as having promoted some form of ethical egoism.3

In recent years, Christian philosopher and theologian Philip R. West has argued that deontological ethics do not capture biblical morality and that ethical egoism is the correct normative theory in this regard. Says West, They [the OT writers] apparently believed not only that actual divine punishment is enough to establish the obligation to obey divine commands, but like Paul, that the absence of actual divine punishment erodes the obligatory status of these commands.4 Elsewhere, West defends the thesis that some agent A has a moral obligation to do P if and only if doing P will maximize As own self-interest. He argues that since scripture grounds our obligations in self-interest (rewards/punishments), this amounts to ethical egoism.

What should we make of this claim? Is ethical egoism the correct normative theory from a biblical point of view? My purpose in what follows is to show why ethical egoism is a defective normative ethical theory and, given this conclusion, to offer ways to understand biblical self-interest that do not entail the truth of ethical egoism. In what follows, I will, first, clarify the precise nature of ethical egoism; second, summarize the main types of arguments for and against ethical egoism in the literature and conclude that ethical egoism is inadequate; third, offer a set of distinctions for understanding biblical self-interest while avoiding ethical egoism.

The most plausible form of ethical egoism, embraced by philosophers such as Ayn Rand and John Hospers, is called universal or impersonal rule-egoism (hereafter, simply ethical egoism). Since Hospers is the most prominent philosopher to advocate ethical egoism, his definition is the most pertinent: each person has a moral duty to follow those moral rules that will be in the agents maximal self-interest over the long haul.5 For the ethical egoist, one has a duty to follow correct moral rules. And the factor that makes a rule a correct one is that, if followed, it will be in the agents own best interests in the long run. Each person ought to advance his own self-interests and that is the sole foundation of morality.

Ethical egoism is sometimes confused and identified with various distinct issues. First, there is individual or personal ethical egoism which says everyone has a duty to act so as to serve my self-interests. Here, everyone is morally obligated to serve the speakers long term best interests. Second, there is psychological egoism, roughly, the idea that each person can only do that act which the person takes to maximize his or her own self-interest. Psychological egoism is a descriptive thesis about motivation to the effect that we can only act on motives that are in our own self-interests. As we shall see shortly, psychological egoism is sometimes used as part of an argument for ethical egoism, but the two are distinct theses.

Third, ethical egoism is not the same thing as egotism an irritating character trait of always trying to be the center of attention. Nor is it the same as what is sometimes called being a wanton. A wanton has no sense of duty at all, but only acts to satisfy his or her own desires. The only conflict the wanton knows is that between two or more desires he cannot simultaneously satisfy (e.g. to eat more and lose weight). The wanton knows nothing about duty. Arguably, animals are wantons. Fifth, ethical egoism is not to be confused with being an egoist, i.e. being someone who believes that the sole worth of an act is its fairly immediate benefits to the individual himself. With this understanding of ethical egoism as a backdrop, let us look at the arguments for and against ethical egoism that have been preeminent in the literature. A detailed treatment of these arguments is not possible here, but by looking briefly at the main considerations usually brought to bear on ethical egoism, a feel for its strengths and weaknesses as a normative ethical theory emerges.

Among the arguments for ethical egoism, two have distinguished themselves, at least in textbook treatments of the position.6 First, it is argued that ethical egoism follows from psychological egoism in this way: psychological egoism is true and this implies that we always and cannot help but act egoistically. This is a fact about human motivation and action. Further, ought implies can. If I ought to do x, if I have a duty to do x, then I must be able to do x. If I cannot do something, then I have no duty or responsibility to do it. Applied to egoism, this means that since I can act egoistically, then I have a d
uty to do so and since I cannot act non-egoistically, then I have no duty to do so. Thus, ethical egoism is the correct picture of moral obligation in keeping with what we know about human motivation.

Does this argument work? Most philosophers have not thought so. First, the principle of psychological egoism, viz. that we always act to maximize our own self-interest, is ambiguous. So stated, the principle falls to make a distinction between the result of an act vs. the intent of an act. If it is understood in the former way it is irrelevant and if taken in the latter way it is false. If the statement merely asserts that, as a matter of fact, the result of our actions is the maximization of self-interest, then this does not imply ethical egoism. Ethical egoism is the view that the thing which morally justifies an act is the agents intent to maximize his own self-interests. So the mere psychological fact (if it is a fact) that people only do those acts that result in their own satisfaction proves nothing.

On the other hand, if the statement claims that we always act solely with the intent to satisfy our own desires, then this claim is simply false. Every day we are aware of doing acts with the sole intent of helping someone else, of doing something just because we think it is the right thing to do, and of expressing virtuous, other-centered behavior. As Christian phiosopher Joseph Butler (1692-1752) argued:

Mankind has various instincts and principles of action as brute creatures have; Some leading most directly and immediately to the good of the community, and some most directly to private good [I]t is not a true representation of mankind, to affirm that they are wholly governed by self-love, the love of power and sensual appetites . it is manifest fact, that the same persons, the generality, are frequently influenced by friendship, compassion, gratitude; and liking of what is fair and just, takes its turn amongst the other motives of action.7

Furthermore, it is not even true that we always try to do what we want or what we think is in our self-interests. We sometimes experience akrasia (weakness of will) when we fail to do or even try to do what we want (see Rom 7:15-25). And we sometimes do (or try to do) our duty even when we dont want to do it. These points appear to be facts about human action.

Second, this argument for ethical egoism suffers from what has been called the paradox of hedonism. Often, the best way maximize self-interest, say, to get happiness and the satisfaction of desire is not to aim at it. Happiness is not usually achieved as an intended goal, but rather, it is a bi-product of a life well lived and of doing what is right. If people always act in order to gain happiness, then it will remain forever elusive. Thus, psychological egoism contains a paradox when viewed as a model of human intention and action.

Finally, as a model of human action, psychological egoism rules out the possibility of libertarian freedom of the will. Briefly put, it should be noted that if libertarian freedom of the will is the correct view of human action, then the following implications follow: 1) no amount of internal states (e.g. desires, beliefs, emotions) are sufficient to produce behavior, and 2) the agent himself must spontaneously exercise his causal powers and act for the sake of reasons which function as teleological goals. For libertarians, a free act is never determined by any particular reason, including desire. Thus, on this view, psychological egoism is false if taken as a total account of human action because it implies that a person must always act for a self-interested reason. Libertarian freedom is controversial and not everyone accepts this model of human action. But the point is that for those who do, it counts as a counter-argument to psychological egoism.

A second argument for ethical egoism is called the closet utilitarian position. Some point out that if everyone acted in keeping with ethical egoism, the result would be the maximization of happiness for the greatest number of people. If acted upon, ethical egoism, as a matter of fact, leads to the betterment of humanity. There are two main problems with this argument. First, it amounts to a utilitarian justification of ethical egoism. Utilitarianism is a normative ethical theory to the effect that a moral action or rule is correct if and only if performing that act or following that rule maximizes the greatest amount of non-moral good vs. bad for the greatest number compared to alternative acts or rules open to the agent. While both are consequentialist in orientation, nevertheless, utilitarianism and ethical egoism are rival normative theories. It is inconsistent, therefore, for someone to use a rival theory, in this case, utilitarianism, as the moral justification for ethical egoism. If one is an ethical egoist, why should he or she care about the greatest good for the greatest number for its own sake, and not merely because such caring would itself lead to greater satisfaction of ones individual desires? Second, the claim seems to be factually false. Is it really the case that if everyone acted according to ethical egoism, it would maximize everyones happiness? Surely not. Sometimes self-sacrifice is needed to maximize happiness for the greatest number, and this argument for ethical egoism cannot allow for personal denial.

There are other arguments for ethical egoism, but these two have been the most central for those who advocate this normative theory. As we have seen, both arguments fail. By contrast, the main arguments against ethical egoism seem to be strong enough to justify rejecting the system as an adequate normative theory.

Among the arguments against ethical egoism, three are most prominent. First, is the publicity objection. Moral principles must serve as action guides that inform moral situations. Most moral situations involve more than one person and, in this sense, are public situations. Thus, moral action guides must be teachable to others so they can be publically used principles that help us in our interpersonal moral interactions. However, according to ethical egoism itself, there is a possible world where it is immoral for me to teach others to embrace ethical egoism because that could easily turn out not to be in my own self-interest. It may be better for me if others always acted altruistically. Thus, it could be immoral for one to go public and teach ethical egoism to others and, if so, this would violate one of the necessary conditions for a moral theory, namely, that it be teachable to others.

Philosopher Fred Feldman has offered a rejoinder to this argument.8 He claims that we have no good reason to believe that a moral doctrine needs to be consistently promulgatable. Why, he asks, should we have to be able to teach a moral doctrine to others? Someone could consistently hold to the following moral notion P as a part of his overall moral system: it is never right to promulgate anything. Unfortunately, this response fails because it does not capture the public nature of moral principles (or normative ethical theories) in so far as they serve as action guides to adjudicate interpersonal moral conflict. How could the principle it is never right to promulgate anything serve as an action guide sufficient to deal with the various aspects of duty, virtue, and rights that constitute much of the point of action guides in the first place?

Moreover, this response fails to take into account the universalizability of moral rules. If I should never promulgate anything, then this implies that I should not teach something to someone else. But there
does not seem to be a clear moral difference in this case between others and myself. To be consistent, then, I should not proclaim this moral principle to myself. Perhaps I should try to hide from myself the fact that I accept this role. This implies, among other things, that if I hold to P as a moral principle that should be universalized, then, applying P to myself, I would no longer have moral grounds for continuing to embrace P on the basis of reasons known to me or for making P known to myself. I should do my best to forget P or talk myself out of believing P. On the other hand, if I do not think P should be universalized, then in what sense is P a moral principle (since universalizability is most likely a necessary condition for a principle counting as moral)?

A second argument against ethical egoism is called the paradox of egoism. Some things, e.g. altruism, deep love, genuine friendship, are inconsistent with ethical egoism. Why? Because these features of a virtuous, moral life require us not to seek our own interests but, rather, those of others. Moreover, ethical egoism would seem to imply that helping others at ones own expense (and other acts of self sacrifice) is wrong if it is not in my long term self-interest to do so. Thus, egoism would seem to rule out important, central features of the moral life. The main point of a normative moral theory is to explain and not to eliminate what we already know to be central facets of morality prior to ethical theorizing. Furthermore, in order to reach the goal of egoism (e.g., personal happiness), one must give up egoism and be altruistic in love, friendship, and other ways. Thus, egoism is paradoxical in its own right and it eliminates key aspects of the moral life.

Some respond by claiming that altruism is fully consistent with ethical egoism. Hospers argues that, according to ethical egoism, we ought to do acts that benefit others because that is in our own self-interests.9 In a similar vein, Fred Feldman asserts that egoism allows us to perform altruistic actions provided that such actions are ultimately in our own self-interests.10 But this response fails to distinguish pseudo-altruism from genuine altruism.

Genuine altruism requires that an altruistic act have, as its sole, or at least main intent, the benefit of the other. An act whose sole or ultimate intent is self-interest but which, nevertheless, does result in the benefit of others is not genuine altruism. If you found out that someone loved you or acted altruistically toward you solely or ultimately with the intent of benefiting himself, then you would not count that as genuine love or altruism even if the act happened to benefit you in some way. Thus, egoistic altruism is a contradiction in terms. Ethical egoism is consistent with pseudo-altruism but not with genuine altruism.

Finally, a third objection claims that ethical egoism leads to inconsistent outcomes. A moral theory must allow for moral rules that are public and universalizable. But ethical egoism could lead to situations where this is not the case. How? Consider two persons A and B in a situation where they have a conflict of interest. For example, suppose there was only one kidney available for transplant, that A and B both need it, and that A or B will die without the transplant. According to universal ethical egoism, A ought to act in his own self-interests and prescribe that his desires come out on top. A had a duty to secure the kidney and thwart Bs attempts to do the same. This would seem to imply that A should prescribe that B has a duty to act in As self-interest. Of course B, according to universal ethical egoism, has from his perspective a duty to act in his own self-interest. But now a contradiction arises because ethical egoism implies that B both has a duty to give the kidney to A and obtain it himself.

Jesse Kalin has responded to this argument by claiming that, as an ethical egoist, A should not hold that B should act in As self-interest, but in Bs own self- interest.11 This would seem to solve the problem of contradictory duty above by rejecting individual ethical egoism (everyone should act in my self-interest) in favor of the universal version (everyone should act in his own self-interest). But this way of stating ethical egoism does not seem to capture the egoistic spirit of the ethical egoism because it leaves open the question as to why egoist A would need to hold that B should act in Bs interests and not in As. In other words, it may not be in As own self-interests to hold to universal, as opposed to individual ethical egoism.

Moreover, there is still a problem for this formulation of ethical egoism which can be brought out as follows: A holds that B has a duty to obtain the kidney for himself, have his interests come out on top, and, thus, harm A. But in this case, ethical egoism still seems to imply an inconsistent posture on As (and Bs) part, namely, that A thinks that B has a duty to get the kidney and harm A but that A has a duty to thwart B. Any moral theory that implies that someone has a moral duty to keep others from doing their moral duty is surely in trouble, so the objection goes. And it is hard to see how an ethical egoist A could claim that someone else had a duty to harm A himself.

Not everyone accepts this argument. Following Kalin, Louis Pojman claims that we often find it to be the case that we have a duty to thwart what is the duty of others, e.g., in a war one soldier has a duty to thwart anothers efforts to do his duty to win. In a case like this, soldiers on different sides do not believe that the other side has adequate moral grounds for being at war.12 If we separate beliefs about ethical situations from desires, so the response goes, then one person can believe the other had a duty to win the war or get the kidney, but the person can also desire to these objectives for himself and act on those desires. In general, the belief that B ought to do x does not imply that A wants B to do x.

What should we make of this response? First, the soldier example fails because it does not distinguish between subjective and objective duty. Subjective duty is one someone has when he has done his best to discover what is and is not the right thing to do. If someone sincerely and conscientiously tries to ascertain what is right, and acts on this, then he has fulfilled his subjective duty and, in a sense, is praiseworthy. But people can be sincerely wrong and fail to live up to their objective duty-the truly correct thing to do from Gods perspective, the overriding moral obligation when all things, including prima facie duties, have been taken into account-even if they have tried to do their best. Admittedly, it is not always easy to determine what the correct objective duty is in a given case. But this is merely an epistemological point and, while valid, it does not negate the legitimacy of the distinction between subjective and objective duty.

Applied to the question at hand, soldier A could only claim that soldier B has both a prima facie duty and a subjective duty to obey his country. But A could also believe that B has an objective duty to do so only if Bs country is, in fact, conducting a morally justified war. Now either A or B is on the right side of the war even though it may be hard to tell which side is correct. Thus, A and B could believe that only one of them actually has an objective duty to fight and thwart the other. So the war example does not give a genuine case where A believes B has a (objective) duty to fight and that he has to thwart B.

Second, what should we make of the claim that we should separate our beliefs about anothers dut
y from the desire to see that duty done? For one thing, a main point of a moral theory is to describe what a virtuous person is and how we can become such persons. Now, one aspect of a virtuous person is that there is a harmony and unity between desire and duty. A virtuous person desires that the objective moral right be done. Such a person is committed to the good and the right. With this in mind, it becomes clear that ethical egoism, if consistently practiced, could produce fragmented, non-virtuous individuals who believe one thing about duty (e.g., A believes B ought to do x) but who desire something else altogether (e.g., A does not desire B to do x).

However, if we grant that the ethical egoists distinction between beliefs and desires is legitimate from a moral point of view, then this distinction does resolve the claim that ethical egoism leads to a conflict of desire, e.g., A desires the kidney and that B obtain the kidney, since it implies that A believes that B has a duty to receive the kidney but only desires that he himself have it. Nevertheless, this misses the real point of the objection to ethical egoism, namely, that ethical egoism straightforwardly leads to a conflict of desire. Rather, the objection shows that ethical egoism leads to an unresolvable conflict of moral beliefs and moral duty. If A and B are ethical egoists, then A believes that it is wrong for B to have the kidney but also that it is Bs duty to try to obtain it. But how can A consistently believe that B has a duty to do something wrong? And how can A have an objective duty to thwart Bs objective duty?

It would seem, then, that ethical egoism should be rejected as a normative ethical theory and that legitimate self-interest is part of Biblical teaching, e.g. in the passages relating moral obligation to rewards and punishments. If we should not understand these texts as implicitly affirming ethical egoism, how should we understand the self-interest they apparently advocate? I do not think that exegesis alone can solve this problem because the context and grammar of the passages are usually not precise enough to settle the philosophical issue before us. However, if we assume with the majority of thinkers that deontological and virtue ethics, and not ethical egoism, are the correct normative theories implied by Scripture, then we have a set of distinctions that provide a number of legitimate ways of understanding biblical self-interest.

To begin with, we need to distinguish between self-benefit as a bi-product of an act vs. self-interest as the sole intent of an act. Scriptural passages that use self-interest may simply be pointing out that if you intentionally do the right thing, then a good bi-product of this will be rewards of various kinds. It could be argued against philosopher Philip R. West (mentioned earlier) that these passages do not clearly use self-interest as the sole legitimate intent of a moral action.

This observation relates to a second distinction between a motive and a reason. Put roughly, a motive is some state within a person that influences and moves him to action. By contrast, a reason is something that serves to justify rationally some belief that one has or some action one does; a reason for believing or doing x is an attempt to cite something that makes it likely that x be true or that x should be done. In this context, just because something, say self-interest, serves as a motive for an action, it does not follow that it also serves as the reason which justifies the action in the first place. Self-interest may be a legitimate motive for moral action, but, it could be argued, Gods commands, the objective moral law, etc. could be rationally cited as the things that make an act our duty in the first place. The Bible may be citing selfinterest as a motive for action and not as the reason for what makes the act our duty.

Moreover, even if Scripture is teaching that self-interest is a reason for doing some duty, it may be offering self-interest as a prudential and not a moral reason for doing the duty. In other words, the Bible may be saying that it is wise, reasonable, and a matter of good judgment to avoid hell and seek rewards without claiming that these considerations are moral reasons for acting according to self-interest.13 In sum, it could be argued that Scripture can be understood as advocating self-interest as a bi-product and not an intent for action, as a motive and not a reason, or as a prudential and not a moral reason. If this is so, then these scriptural ideas do not entail ethical egoism.

Second, even if scripture teaches that self-interest contributes to making something my moral duty, ethical egoism still does not follow. For one thing, ethical egoism teaches that an act is moral if and only if it maximizes my own self-interests. Ethical egoism teaches that self-interest is both necessary and sufficient for something to be my duty. However, it could be argued that egoistic factors, while not alone morally relevant to an act (other things like self-sacrifice or obeying God for its own sake are relevant as well), nevertheless, are at least one feature often important for assessing the moral worth of an act. Moral duty is not exhausted by self-interest as ethical egoism implies, but self-interest can be a legitimate factor in moral deliberation and scripture may be expressing this point.

Additionally, it is likely that the precise nature of self-interest contained in scripture is different in two ways from that which forms part of ethical egoism. For one thing, according to ethical egoism, the thing that makes an act right is that it is in my self-interest. The important value-making property here is the fact that something promotes the first person interests of the actor. Here, the moral agent attends to himself precisely as being identical to himself and to no one else.

By contrast, the scriptural emphasis on self-interest most likely grounds the appropriateness of such interest, not in the mere fact that these interests are mine, but in the fact that I am a creature of intrinsic value made in Gods image and, as such, ought to care about what happens to me. Here I seek my own welfare not because it is my own, but because of what I am, viz. a creature with high intrinsic value. Consider a possible world where human persons have no value whatever (or where human counter-parts with no intrinsic value exist). In that world, ethical egoism would still legislate self-interest, but the second view under consideration (that self-interest follows from the fact that I am a creature of value) would not because the necessary condition for self-interest (being a creature of intrinsic value) does not obtain in that world.

There is a second way that the nature of self-interest in Scripture and in ethical egoism differ. As C. S. Lewis and C. Stephen Evans have argued, there are different kinds of rewards, and some are proper because they have a natural, intrinsic connection with the things we do to earn them and because they are expressions of what God made us to be by nature. 14 In such cases, these rewards provide a reason to do an activity which does not despoil the character of the activity itself. Money is not a natural reward for love (one is mercenary to marry for money) because money is foreign to the desires that ought to accompany love. By contrast, victory is a natural reward for battle. It is a proper reward because it is not tacked onto the activity for which the reward is given, but rather victory is the consummation of and intrinsically related to the activity itself.

According to Lewis, the desire for heaven and rewards is a natural desire express
ing what we, by nature, are. We were made to desire honor before God, to be in his presence, and to hunger to enjoy the rewards he will offer us and these things are the natural consummations of our activity on earth. Thus, the appropriateness of seeking heaven and rewards derives from the fact that these results are genuine expressions of our natures and are the natural consummation of our activities for God. By contrast, according to ethical egoism, the value of results has nothing to do with our natures or with natural consummations of activities. Rather, the worth of those outcomes is solely a function of the fact that they benefit the agent himself.

In sum, self-interest is part of biblical teaching, especially in association with rewards and punishments. But ethical egoism neither captures adequately the nature of biblical self-interest nor is it the best normative ethical theory in its own right. As Christians, we should include self-interest as an important part of our moral and religious lives but without advocating ethical egoism in the process.

With degrees in philosophy, theology and chemisty, Dr. Moreland brings erudition, passion, and his distinctive ebullience to the end of loving God with all of one's mind. Moreland received his B.S. in Chemistry (with honors) from the University of Missouri, his M.A. in Philosophy (with highest honors) from the University of California, Riverside, his Th.M. in Theology (with honors) from Dallas Theological Seminary and his Ph.D. in Philosophy from the University of Southern California. Dr. Moreland has taught theology and philosophy at several schools throughout the U.S. He is currently Distinguished Professor of Philosophy at Biola University's Talbot School of Theology.

Read more:

Ethical Egoism and Biblical Self-Interest | Papers at ...

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ethical Egoism and Biblical Self-Interest | Papers at …

Ethical Egoism – University of Colorado Boulder

Posted: June 17, 2016 at 4:52 am

%PDF-1.4 % 1 0 obj << /Title (Ethical Egoism) /Author (Chad Vance) /Creator (Microsoft Word 2010) /ModDate (D:20130110142849-07'00') /Producer (http://www.convertapi.com ) /CreationDate (D:20130110142830-07'00') /PXCViewerInfo (PDF-XChange Viewer;2.5.199.0;Sep 27 2011;19:41:29;D:20130110142849-07'00') >> endobj 2 0 obj << /Lang (en-US) /Type /Catalog /Pages 3 0 R /MarkInfo << /Marked true >> /Metadata 4 0 R /StructTreeRoot 5 0 R /ViewerPreferences 6 0 R >> endobj 3 0 obj << /Kids [7 0 R 8 0 R 9 0 R 10 0 R 11 0 R 12 0 R] /Type /Pages /Count 6 >> endobj 4 0 obj << /Type /Metadata /Length 3706 /Subtype /XML >> stream http://www.convertapi.com 2013-01-10T14:28:49-07:00 2013-01-10T15:28:30-06:00 2013-01-10T15:28:30-06:00 Microsoft Word 2010 application/pdf Chad Vance Ethical Egoism uuid:75980C92-338C-C991-EA74-4D50B5D65939 uuid:E861E6C5-6265-7741-C4CF-A69C8A2573D5 endstream endobj 5 0 obj << /K [13 0 R] /Type /StructTreeRoot /RoleMap 14 0 R /ParentTree 15 0 R /ParentTreeNextKey 8 >> endobj 6 0 obj << /FitWindow false /HideMenubar false /HideToolbar false /CenterWindow false /HideWindowUI false >> endobj 7 0 obj << /Tabs /S /Type /Page /Group << /S /Transparency /CS /DeviceRGB /Type /Group >> /Parent 3 0 R /Contents 16 0 R /MediaBox [0 0 612 792] /Resources << /Font << /F1 17 0 R /F2 18 0 R /F3 19 0 R /F4 20 0 R /F5 21 0 R /F6 22 0 R >> /ProcSet [/PDF /Text /ImageB /ImageC /ImageI] /ExtGState << /GS7 23 0 R >> >> /StructParents 0 >> endobj 8 0 obj << /Tabs /S /Type /Page /Group << /S /Transparency /CS /DeviceRGB /Type /Group >> /Parent 3 0 R /Contents 24 0 R /MediaBox [0 0 612 792] /Resources << /Font << /F1 17 0 R /F2 18 0 R /F4 20 0 R >> /ProcSet [/PDF /Text /ImageB /ImageC /ImageI] >> /StructParents 1 >> endobj 9 0 obj << /Tabs /S /Type /Page /Group << /S /Transparency /CS /DeviceRGB /Type /Group >> /Annots [25 0 R 26 0 R] /Parent 3 0 R /Contents 27 0 R /MediaBox [0 0 612 792] /Resources << /Font << /F1 17 0 R /F2 18 0 R /F3 19 0 R /F4 20 0 R /F5 21 0 R >> /ProcSet [/PDF /Text /ImageB /ImageC /ImageI] >> /StructParents 2 >> endobj 10 0 obj << /Tabs /S /Type /Page /Group << /S /Transparency /CS /DeviceRGB /Type /Group >> /Parent 3 0 R /Contents 28 0 R /MediaBox [0 0 612 792] /Resources << /Font << /F1 17 0 R /F2 18 0 R /F3 19 0 R /F4 20 0 R /F5 21 0 R /F7 29 0 R >> /ProcSet [/PDF /Text /ImageB /ImageC /ImageI] >> /StructParents 5 >> endobj 11 0 obj << /Tabs /S /Type /Page /Group << /S /Transparency /CS /DeviceRGB /Type /Group >> /Parent 3 0 R /Contents 30 0 R /MediaBox [0 0 612 792] /Resources << /Font << /F1 17 0 R /F2 18 0 R /F4 20 0 R /F5 21 0 R /F7 29 0 R >> /ProcSet [/PDF /Text /ImageB /ImageC /ImageI] >> /StructParents 6 >> endobj 12 0 obj << /Tabs /S /Type /Page /Group << /S /Transparency /CS /DeviceRGB /Type /Group >> /Parent 3 0 R /Contents 31 0 R /MediaBox [0 0 612 792] /Resources << /Font << /F1 17 0 R /F2 18 0 R /F3 19 0 R /F4 20 0 R /F5 21 0 R /F8 32 0 R >> /ProcSet [/PDF /Text /ImageB /ImageC /ImageI] >> /StructParents 7 >> endobj 13 0 obj << /K [33 0 R 34 0 R 35 0 R 36 0 R 37 0 R 38 0 R 39 0 R 40 0 R 41 0 R 42 0 R 43 0 R 44 0 R 45 0 R 46 0 R 47 0 R 48 0 R 49 0 R 50 0 R 51 0 R 52 0 R 53 0 R 54 0 R 55 0 R 56 0 R 57 0 R 58 0 R 59 0 R 60 0 R 61 0 R 62 0 R 63 0 R 64 0 R 65 0 R 66 0 R 67 0 R 68 0 R 69 0 R 70 0 R 71 0 R 72 0 R 73 0 R 74 0 R 75 0 R 76 0 R 77 0 R 78 0 R 79 0 R 80 0 R 81 0 R 82 0 R 83 0 R 84 0 R 85 0 R 86 0 R 87 0 R 88 0 R 89 0 R 90 0 R 91 0 R 92 0 R 93 0 R 94 0 R 95 0 R 96 0 R 97 0 R 98 0 R 99 0 R 100 0 R 101 0 R] /P 5 0 R /S /Part /Type /StructElem >> endobj 14 0 obj << /Chart /Sect /Slide /Part /Footer /Sect /Header /Sect /Diagram /Figure /Endnote /Note /Textbox /Sect /Artifact /Sect /Footnote /Note /Workbook /Document /Worksheet /Part /Annotation /Sect /Chartsheet /Part /Macrosheet /Part /Dialogsheet /Part /InlineShape /Sect >> endobj 15 0 obj << /Nums [0 102 0 R 1 103 0 R 2 104 0 R 3 105 0 R 4 105 0 R 5 106 0 R 6 107 0 R 7 108 0 R] >> endobj 16 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 3338 >> stream xZn8}7/,t `g6"X$ }n~DfY,Oy~y|Y_VU|*Wm~?{Ur~NOoYxpxz @awhs'Q_OO/'7 0ea e0fYp(NOlx(N+o+e{!F?,'> 8F3bO.W, #/v3 JuP0O[G+wy";2,XY/s5{s9;IVOsA:) 5%cnMP*(Q$ UEW(ElbAzOmkHJ^+A.2|upv!kmPTe$cPuCeAGn+#Pf1'a^4d`Y, "Ae*$}5@.?7 #4KN~DOW;zzM80pl1 '#>E wyuCw8/$<$-AZ:c5<||y(Wd*#`-dfkd-mQb^peYQobZ-CVC`pkr1Wk|Dg@b yaiTFlP]UnF1tusL9jMP jFx$!Sjti"^)VCosH`p6PI_(p!oxDJCnCy}/2;8rCP=G bvTWC,3F-1-I myGgt7nM45Pz0 gV2hFXC1ALb$xpGE8^@"tAfL:l16by'#c5AH:i3TX ;il8&/*."L6>|(,r+7&Dz*3X :>" j D Ses 0)J.kf2o8PC fHbWWXKo]gP3o&QGMl@*@z:#?vKx+Vvv`P(12(%$vSLH}4s8cQj &~r[YJ|0[ !%`O8X0D{$2AnqCh<7u6m= Li c+ot=y YMLMUB{TKcbet(=!@ b$D}IYWJ_%JaiTE aneXMk^pu-jmx{||n3ep#)<;N=)=i*wklVqN'!)k Zb9dW[ 1pK .`9 {sw]8Q"NHF+',>1kN&h_5({ f>8j=SKdsi6vN5aAXu S=QL H~DjaC39o"z8iwX:"EV> endobj 18 0 obj << /Name /F2 /Type /Font /Widths 111 0 R /Subtype /TrueType /BaseFont /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI /Encoding /WinAnsiEncoding /LastChar 121 /FirstChar 32 /FontDescriptor 112 0 R >> endobj 19 0 obj << /Name /F3 /Type /Font /Widths 113 0 R /Subtype /TrueType /BaseFont /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI,Bold /Encoding /WinAnsiEncoding /LastChar 121 /FirstChar 32 /FontDescriptor 114 0 R >> endobj 20 0 obj << /Type /Font /Subtype /Type0 /BaseFont /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI /Encoding /Identity-H /ToUnicode 115 0 R /DescendantFonts 116 0 R >> endobj 21 0 obj << /Name /F5 /Type /Font /Widths 117 0 R /Subtype /TrueType /BaseFont /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI,Italic /Encoding /WinAnsiEncoding /LastChar 121 /FirstChar 32 /FontDescriptor 118 0 R >> endobj 22 0 obj << /Type /Font /Subtype /Type0 /BaseFont /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI,Bold /Encoding /Identity-H /ToUnicode 119 0 R /DescendantFonts 120 0 R >> endobj 23 0 obj << /BM /Normal /ca 1 /Type /ExtGState >> endobj 24 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 3470 >> stream xZYoG~8%% l'0;#rHM+"wLre>?u>)w?|UnmSv{7cO|y,sY:i6.[??]^|{EN p/c,cUqy;m44Fq^&/rfh78M>s"l??c7s- %nxb7x@bq8c#<`Wh6TuY]=br9Dr _$D:7Iu F:[11fIh/Md3R!Y|>>')Xx#YK!_dp1i2}HlKP ?MT(,#nb^;}k1^{0/"'<+~DAxNKP.xWCNY}2 Mm':7~c3U`92AF|:9nTsfjp p/;?9o3!l-F 1E_>!6H]fPDR(D$qPbw$RKvdVL##CIaXwp"(%P)QhWQpH~7^3xy`0EaD*mx!jo}NtF.kg 0+A%G#})//FBd b 8sHr/#@G|'6{A/9L*g}#nCX5NR>$ Q}%*,T-L]wj&nF;4f3mB*E'C%hR5pyNL]5'^aB-l:9m$ FRhqZJH*47rG b O3C(CK$!$g_((q[k^hBpeN(PoC/r7HTcm8 ~NPm]&Z$ -x["TBk73GnjDhxRT GsF)_^!W[>nBr*g{3'nCog, 7Je Xj8R'S=A/a:zX c+(F3E(T>D)"sgLQmO9LFr-83Lfr/2R@p5RCR]_1+ IWF"sBTKaAD% gN3"n`wZQT~mMB7qb` Q1S$v^e`qTx9GSi dql ZB,$j$!GIcIumv|Uf=~whH?7c b7 C[c[}]orY"F|$Z=b91]T,i+lt_F^s;0@C7cm$?Bdn]fKC 88NV =EzdLYyF4U]1G1C^h8sghV 6ZbHb;Q`]rd}YUa*{2+ ;^ VVg6ony>/ht#j__WQOHV]nYfF;0Y6)(Hfd#xSz7$^F(*c]OZlDF$nve0!Yb0In>Dz-~NAST{K >ayShxDU6%tHLgV^7gio5.7+?Y>W"! R6 dB!3 n7^.p0UIWtNH5 N[^t(a#l:2 -@W:Ll$[q#epvWpg6,+R[mdVsuxYcfe/up-Nw]O'*Dck endstream endobj 25 0 obj << /A << /S /URI /URI (http://www.cnn.com/2012/08/14/opinion/weiss-ryan-rand/index.html) /Type /Action >> /F 4 /BS << /W 0 >> /Rect [255.19 85.301 524.25 98.602] /Subtype /Link /StructParent 3 >> endobj 26 0 obj << /A << /S /URI /URI (http://www.cnn.com/2012/08/14/opinion/weiss-ryan-rand/index.html) /Type /Action >> /F 4 /BS << /W 0 >> /Rect [87.75 72 162.3 85.301] /Subtype /Link /St
ructParent 4 >> endobj 27 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 4126 >> stream xrFUT!f$YoW$B$b2I38H&Gzztz^7}qo7Mq,ml 8x]yK4dS1 0`:'fbt?t0->q)e#D.ohM0%;>C}ZMgrBpfASGp$.1Mapivp9hW BE1^,d~S%>6x6J2[a>)qa'Y3ZJ#9rtxU/-h hXb05O _~%|N[|6f!UrI]kY%!{Oe=,1o[I`g) ~2<4DNKz6KX#pIBVjjm`'Grfm!cGc n4L(t=UCMF'I5&j'kvF"?^Y=bJ - p6 |7cYfm@`9~^.[>s>;]Z1Q4|CDSiHS~KR0??bFA=qp)qh'p9$xQ Fab|o^&?geBvU-Q9 y*ke(",lVY5;JRA mDG]R?^@@8ab!lMY5/G|@i2.D'4RsY<$Nk(wc9*m)PqNJNbN6fD"zq`5y>/K:&i;595Tybur+4ESI<<#p >oB{.e.# R!cH&$W/61^'I>MrU}t#C emh@IVE`aB Q$+Eo^0eB3KO:xE! ouPEyGe*4}%GE{%YK9X:<}l(+BV`A81iN,/X05i#g%nGq);4Qy||FBV>mn%kotb;m1pj3SKP'-)zhN~WqTE66aUot1&H|0hR e_h^i{mG"i@)fPx r mw@ YTl7 n|m2`/Fso~6vhVN/HzLB7qVTIg(aH52Bc7aRqO]-6{e3RO'=Xf&{"$4(|K[ 8@;52) .ma]Xs04pC2tbM3/dG4`ymyMGvAcYhlW<{ ymN)p s]?Ofukq_s7uuVqHY"JHCuz&~TR.L];s$Om(1Xh{> stream xZ[o6~GQuYHd(>(lk[eA}9C/e{hOH7}{-j>lvcW.M{=_>s#2,qVA%,<6NF2BoCno9wjD]4j >UVr!=mUzWk6T6v5%.|<e^yFJg!MVL/8GIYj,tp4Ktjn?kIQ)l@e@wj2 :f or 3dX"@`< G3SY5]vYm? {360d:Q]qf}Xqa*.vUDejFN[@(]^eji~g702DgK$LHYuc,KVNg5[AcVmi@pN:j:!a^ WiXew=5i66zi6)fl!(Nq/X@.x7^W2U);0Iz:c~f ~|~!Ib14=MS=H^Uygg /<4A~[5C'!t='i^ 4KB< @^[M>$DV`/"jnpFhbB'!mO#6,W;i v]9tie'xPLSp7 y1f Q=:Kt>(`4Wj)}*AkmQjU/J:`*"(2"uu,'XPmt7Z3oikj"+0[:jEUf4ORDH;gcq~V;EU 4&;5&RaC=SmPSwvyaLkE7 #s.Ex>]Q9o:APqd]h,zb]$aT1zRX&yNa$gX`^v)'2#J@)wM"n@>fZTDw]M)?v(eh5xESI E+,u]d"d"^{( ^Q[ ,Y) [$U U BB.{Zl9e0x1!|&9yM{@sdV*,3U" 2g$ ._9<4$g 9Sw3NS(#r"()?=W@~A)?kB)Ru{2.,TVYV7dz`fS-+FT_OCdSqz7q;F}j.}v.Q-`0wSudw#|.QDL-{3/=w'N 9_p|xR}Q@ Os5-C0<7G$ :wBO |/>Lt`K..I `urvl`>7]va#w:~C <05).[tBW0Ir{5y >J]urn_Q[78}EI2 J3 c#[Xt{A> endobj 30 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 3132 >> stream xZms8~obE/M'$Mvmzin:~Pl/9YI&HiH 7M1~,'iV?NZMZ:A(G_ rC)2q8>r|m "?@DH< !oKRpQo_[|#^x)gw8P~, >$ikxStz^Ig/(,Hxc@DFr0+O7'fE@|8*:(>R^gbqC>a]'}7F5 FSs3@.WJaj#Job-dc~PQ|TZ*hv;,L1'Uk=4]jyyXCmlAM`wy*7xWhtzu%{$?WUAV<< k@Kn}Q)X ?"FnisdDerV`,P"T1NsO& )N w$'Mv9SK o/'v/:(*Q*)au NmIYI 0JDUwi^`R#Kqo4MIYY2#~wBVm)'g 4?ZI2;S$g;4l; ! 5[`BIR|I;sV^"K@mQjWJnuvQn'4N#^i]WSax8r'wX /K2(X!=RZ8a$z!@ p2&V+|3,s/]jv=@vIpKvC4Hk3Q>+>~F+t'5b/"r/'Nj'u -^9Swm|^W`NDP588UNI<"}T!;~#hJDH{NmmP[Rhv(hs>~e6jujFXP+T+zYe0yXM)4ITp(KoJjO 'CJiB@WaK/sMlvQsFnc/}/~lF f+T2B*.3&"&"7]K~c%1SUnwuYbOTI l'f>hO(HTOv%'SWMpp7U ~)q>j}+T4L> "7++/n9ERm;z&V5cv.KZPjk#_o-?n K]LPJL~rq

t[A%+.8 -'P$+rs E)!Q endstream endobj 31 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 2042 >> stream xXo8HERE"qE(a}Plm%Gn|3ij],[v}}umWbS9[O//`yX1,cm^^|^(`RT,*cBh?94JpC`0 6e7,jb7"U<.+ lc@C[)vF1Z(JT3YyB@.U_69GJ) 0n'zd9k1C:!u~7>_9cha[`rO=UTvZll> endobj 33 0 obj << /K [0] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 34 0 obj << /K [1] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 35 0 obj << /K [2] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 36 0 obj << /K [3] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 37 0 obj << /K [4] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 38 0 obj << /K [5] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 39 0 obj << /K [6] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 40 0 obj << /K [7] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 41 0 obj << /K [8] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 42 0 obj << /K [9] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 43 0 obj << /K [10] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 44 0 obj << /K [11] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 45 0 obj << /K [12] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 46 0 obj << /K [13] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 47 0 obj << /K [14] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 48 0 obj << /K [15] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 49 0 obj << /K [16] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 50 0 obj << /K [17] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 51 0 obj << /K [18] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 52 0 obj << /K [19] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 53 0 obj << /K [20] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 7 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 54 0 obj << /K [0] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 55 0 obj << /K [1] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 56 0 obj << /K [2] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 57 0 obj << /K [3] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 58 0 obj << /K [4] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 59 0 obj << /K [5] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 60 0 obj << /K [6] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 61 0 obj << /K [7] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 62 0 obj << /K [8] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 63 0 obj << /K [9] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 64 0 obj << /K [10] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 65 0 obj << /K [11] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 8 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 66 0 obj << /K [0] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 67 0 obj << /K [1] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 68 0 obj << /K [2] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 69 0 obj << /K [3] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 70 0 obj << /K [4] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 71 0 obj << /K [125 0 R] /P 13 0 R /S /Footnote /Pg 9 0 R /Type /Struct Elem >> endobj 72 0 obj << /K [5] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 73 0 obj << /K [6] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 74 0 obj << /K [7] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 75 0 obj << /K [8] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 76 0 obj << /K [0] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 77 0 obj << /K [1] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 78 0 obj << /K [2] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 79 0 obj << /K [3] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 80 0 obj << /K [4] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 81 0 obj << /K [5] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 82 0 obj << /K [6] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 83 0 obj << /K [7] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 84 0 obj << /K [8] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 85 0 obj << /K [9] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 86 0 obj << /K [126 0 R] /P 13 0 R /S /L /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 87 0 obj << /K [11] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 88 0 obj << /K [127 0 R] /P 13 0 R /S /L /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 89 0 obj << /K [13] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 90 0 obj << /K [128 0 R] /P 13 0 R /S /L /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 91 0 obj << /K [1] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 92 0 obj << /K [129 0 R] /P 13 0 R /S /L /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 93 0 obj << /K [3] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 94 0 obj << /K [130 0 R] /P 13 0 R /S /L /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 95 0 obj << /K [5] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 96 0 obj << /K [0] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 12 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 97 0 obj << /K [1] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 12 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 98 0 obj << /K [2] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 12 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 99 0 obj << /K [3] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 12 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 100 0 obj << /K [4] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 12 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 101 0 obj << /K [5] /P 13 0 R /S /P /Pg 12 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 102 0 obj [33 0 R 34 0 R 35 0 R 36 0 R 37 0 R 38 0 R 39 0 R 40 0 R 41 0 R 42 0 R 43 0 R 44 0 R 45 0 R 46 0 R 47 0 R 48 0 R 49 0 R 50 0 R 51 0 R 52 0 R 53 0 R] endobj 103 0 obj [54 0 R 55 0 R 56 0 R 57 0 R 58 0 R 59 0 R 60 0 R 61 0 R 62 0 R 63 0 R 64 0 R 65 0 R] endobj 104 0 obj [66 0 R 67 0 R 68 0 R 69 0 R 70 0 R 72 0 R 73 0 R 74 0 R 75 0 R 131 0 R 132 0 R 133 0 R] endobj 105 0 obj << /K [134 0 R 135 0 R 132 0 R] /P 125 0 R /S /Link /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 106 0 obj [76 0 R 77 0 R 78 0 R 79 0 R 80 0 R 81 0 R 82 0 R 83 0 R 84 0 R 85 0 R 136 0 R 87 0 R 137 0 R 89 0 R] endobj 107 0 obj [138 0 R 91 0 R 139 0 R 93 0 R 140 0 R 95 0 R] endobj 108 0 obj [96 0 R 97 0 R 98 0 R 99 0 R 100 0 R 101 0 R] endobj 109 0 obj [250] endobj 110 0 obj << /Type /FontDescriptor /Flags 32 /StemV 40 /Ascent 891 /Descent -216 /Leading 42 /XHeight 250 /AvgWidth 401 /FontBBox [-568 -216 2000 693] /FontName /Times#20New#20Roman /MaxWidth 2568 /CapHeight 693 /FontWeight 400 /ItalicAngle 0 >> endobj 111 0 obj [274 0 0 591 0 0 0 0 302 302 0 0 217 400 217 390 539 539 539 539 539 539 539 539 539 539 217 0 0 0 0 448 0 645 573 619 701 506 488 686 710 266 357 0 471 898 748 754 560 0 598 531 524 687 621 934 0 553 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 509 588 462 589 523 313 589 566 242 242 497 242 861 566 586 588 589 348 424 339 566 479 723 459 484] endobj 112 0 obj << /Type /FontDescriptor /Flags 32 /StemV 53 /Ascent 1079 /Descent -210 /XHeight 250 /AvgWidth 539 /FontBBox [-432 -210 1483 728] /FontName /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI /MaxWidth 1915 /CapHeight 728 /FontFile2 141 0 R /FontWeight 400 /ItalicAngle 0 >> endobj 113 0 obj [276 0 0 592 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 271 0 0 575 575 575 575 0 0 0 0 0 271 0 0 0 0 438 0 703 0 624 0 532 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 790 758 614 0 0 561 586 0 0 1005 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 538 620 480 619 541 383 619 602 284 284 0 284 916 605 611 620 0 398 440 389 605 542 797 0 538] endobj 114 0 obj << /Type /FontDescriptor /Flags 32 /StemV 59 /Ascent 1079 /Descent -210 /XHeight 250 /AvgWidth 590 /FontBBox [-479 -210 1780 728] /FontName /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI,Bold /MaxWidth 2259 /CapHeight 728 /FontFile2 142 0 R /FontWeight 700 /ItalicAngle 0 >> endobj 115 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 384 >> stream x}Sn0>l !B 8,)R1_{CaT 6M<[`W`?MmqPJ,>T3;vH endstream endobj 116 0 obj [143 0 R] endobj 117 0 obj [275 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 218 0 218 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 218 0 0 0 0 0 0 632 0 0 0 499 489 0 0 0 0 0 0 818 0 754 575 0 0 497 526 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 0 542 542 436 542 487 295 542 557 259 240 0 259 858 562 535 542 0 355 395 323 558 473 720 0 484] endobj 118 0 obj << /Type /FontDescriptor /Flags 32 /StemV 54 /Ascent 1079 /Descent -210 /XHeight 250 /AvgWidth 543 /FontBBox [-458 -210 1339 728] /FontName /ABCDEE+Segoe#20UI,Italic /MaxWidth 1797 /CapHeight 728 /FontFile2 144 0 R /FontWeight 400 /ItalicAngle -12 >> endobj 119 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 281 >> stream x]Qn ,8i"A&%Ar=<0#aqsA>| dCi?sm endstream endobj 120 0 obj [145 0 R] endobj 121 0 obj [278] endobj 122 0 obj << /Type /FontDescriptor /Flags 32 /StemV 44 /Ascent 905 /Descent -210 /Leading 33 /XHeight 250 /AvgWidth 441 /FontBBox [-665 -210 2000 728] /FontName /Arial /MaxWidth 2665 /CapHeight 728 /FontWeight 400 /ItalicAngle 0 >> endobj 123 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 322 >> stream xeRn0+|L!Q$TEb)R1q}n=[>w/ endstream endobj 124 0 obj [146 0 R] endobj 125 0 obj << /K [131 0 R 105 0 R 133 0 R] /P 71 0 R /S /P /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 126 0 obj << /K [136 0 R] /P 86 0 R /S /LI /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 127 0 obj << /K [137 0 R] /P 88 0 R /S /LI /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 128 0 obj << /K [138 0 R] /P 90 0 R /S /LI /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 129 0 obj << /K [139 0 R] /P 92 0 R /S /LI /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 130 0 obj << /K [140 0 R] /P 94 0 R /S /LI /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 131 0 obj << /K 9 /P 125 0 R /S /Span /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 132 0 obj << /K 10 /P 105 0 R /S /Span /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 133 0 obj << /K 11 /P 125 0 R /S /Span /Pg 9 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 134 0 obj << /Pg 9 0 R /Obj 25 0 R /Type /OBJR >> endobj 135 0 obj << /Pg 9 0 R /Obj 26 0 R /Type /OBJR >> endobj 136 0 obj << /K [10] /P 126 0 R /S /LBody /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 137 0 obj << /K [12] /P 127 0 R /S /LBody /Pg 10 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 138 0 obj << /K [0] /P 128 0 R /S /LBody /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 139 0 obj << /K [2] /P 129 0 R /S /LBody /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 140 0 obj << /K [4] /P 130 0 R /S /LBody /Pg 11 0 R /Type /StructElem >> endobj 141 0 obj << /Filter [/FlateDecode] /Length 46005 /Length1 146588 >> stream x] `3;Wv Y rYr (G 66EQE`@=QIGo{S&ORZ5[0Og w;mh_0?%s2Y6^[j>J{IR(`q^XFN! g_L#31kl~ l+IO$NV1*J+9(>~`f*l>l19l7s7Np;zK10av,Z^~#8 ^U[0>Ec^"Hpw)lc.A_>sy` wg7zrbzQC|.cb0bXv d|Up}6wSr0l&en|0Ob]woc hawq00 6la 6la 6lq4~a O=w1_ 6l/PN ^4AJT Dub|!=bq=[jmFg;PM9tE'3Pw=6l=8=o.DwlZ24c-DdPUP6pns/AC@Gc~!{-AX! #9;r! "=@9 {B^zC?>/@E1|B.q0 0Xn~Cy(@-.a|!Hs7'@%rT!'0 ND0|`,(|"d7`<& '!aP| u.EkVkvguqxv ?o i>_//#o.W]W-n5xy;|h> [>B~>F|&|#o>G~w|vY.!xX!?" |LDO"#J3 !*h#rbE,'
Ri,'<( $I@xIT$AEEX+!t^a.@tr8"Aa{ #1i U_[~5Zg/(QZFZPdYDZ~EtVr~ A4:_}F &lW8"t_q/j!_-,E?ji __}#wOav;&m8v;_-4A=cAjeDp"At*$9dH^%^8N,(v:74:0?]G[z6l8z`Zy#wOa]+L>/tLqhCpj~C$E*c8 g{2IDUQto6i<^0wp$,I6m0(h> g,;a2..<'Ngnr *]!T]Q;MZ~sR|~>?|@] Gp),KdI6m:h4AEP [^gsry4UsI[b[4YNlo8i@&]9p#(u 6l|[G8r*j&_vtLqh$):MAA]>W~ ye{qN-(Cuh.u&(2;.qzx lG+CqXfJ 6,;4AE_@y`uOG4zq&2]vA( c _v=EPUEwl;$m8djMdjkyy ZP>Wk_n MLl]t6z6r6l6aG8:9;&m8W8ErK._;,CCN#~(xz  pjN'{:M: NWr>?|r-?u@XA(yw=6l=v#wOt]5'^|Ma.MAxYPGO]= K00_+,P+(,,zAg^ M==,KQO 6kp)x;&m8A@Z(Pca|jald32 2K>?NIX6~~1g,n;4w.lFz0l&z2L^t;Kw$&&'r3Q#e'_z9xcw{p~(]s%Q9!0SYPE}JVF5#{|Ho8m:*9+ZMD#F8F/5qkGEb3&9 .4bEjDaV*#Jx4-:6Xf)"%f&aL%RhY15M6|&6`&`{UN0p(33fut1 VbQ&cazR^U3'gUj&fsH 5S!TZ$W>{7:Q([m2RktxJnoE f1RlK5-ZC3:FO Zj;Hih>-L:7jjWeeo}mXG'JWe(zL));|5Z1_1$}*dYO(o+'6%l+k62/me5 tL0hm##YKR XyR.f&2y +/^U3+`dLJscsH<)E"j."l.BY1{--mq.wZ/ZX'-~,j?lXG33kx,^iq+,^fR[Ox-vQM8{98Uv+x9K//,a|EHA:

View post:

Ethical Egoism - University of Colorado Boulder

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ethical Egoism – University of Colorado Boulder

Ethical Egoism – Carnegie Mellon University

Posted: June 13, 2016 at 12:51 pm

Robert Cavalier Philosophy Department Carnegie Mellon

Part I History of Ethics

Preface: The Life of Socrates Section 1: Greek Moral Philosophy Section 2: Hellenistic and Roman Ethics Section 3: Early Christian Ethics Section 4: Modern Moral Philosophy Section 5: 20th Century Analytic Moral Philosophy

Part II Concepts and Problems

Preface: Meta-ethics, Normative Ethics and Applied Ethics Section 1: Ethical Relativism Section 2: Ethical Egoism Section 3: Utilitarian Theories Section 4: Deontological Theories Section 5: Virtue Ethics Section 6: Liberal Rights and Communitarian Theories Section 7: Ethics of Care Section 8: Case-based Moral Reasoning Section 9: Moral Pluralism

Part III Applied Ethics

Preface: The Field of Applied Ethics Section 1: The Topic of Euthanasia Multimedia Module: A Right to Die? The Dax Cowart Case Section 2: The Topic of Abortion Multimedia Module: The Issue of Abortion in America Postscript: Conflict Resolution

As a metaethical theory of motivation, psychological egoism asserts the descriptive claim that all of our actions can be reduced to self-interest: "Whenever people do something, it is only because they think something desirable for themselves will result from it." The claim is descriptive and thus open to counterexamples, and it is broad, stating a reductionistic thesis regarding all of our actions. (Contrast psychological egoism with the psychological state of sympathy, where 'the weal and woe of the other becomes the motive for our action'.)

It is interesting to note that while egoism rests on the principles of human psychology, a number of studies in the psychology of moral development seem to suggest that 'egoism' is in fact only a first stage in actual moral development.

See excerpts from the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on Egoism.

Read more:

Ethical Egoism - Carnegie Mellon University

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ethical Egoism – Carnegie Mellon University

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism

Posted: June 8, 2016 at 2:43 am

Follow

Consequentialism is a moral theory that states that the consequences of one's actions are the basis for any morality or judgment toward that action. Both utilitarianism and ethical egoism are theories within consequentialism that focus on the outcome of conduct as the primary motivation of that action and any critique of whether or not that conduct is ethical. The major difference between utilitarianism and ethical egoism is where those acts are directed.

Utilitarianism focuses on the idea of the greater good. Essentially, this ethical theory intends to maximize good for the the most people. The moral worth of any action is judged by how much good results for all sentient beings. While some individuals may suffer from these actions, utilitarianism holds that the conduct may still be ethical if it does more good for a greater number of people than it harms.

Ethical egoism, also known simply as egoism, holds that moral conduct ought to be judged through self-interest. Egoism states that the good consequences for the individual agent outweigh the consequences placed upon others. In egoism, actions could be considered ethical for the individual if the one taking the action is benefited, while any benefit or detriment to the welfare of others is a side effect and not as important as the consequences for the individual.

The primary differences between these two theories, keeping in mind that there are numerous sub-theories within each branch of thought, is the value placed between the individual and others. In utilitarianism, the most ethical action may be that which harms the individual agent but maximizes the positive impact for the most people overall, essentially placing the emphasis on the whole as opposed to the individual. In egoism, the individual has a greater value than others, thus it is ethical to act in one's own self-interest even if it may potentially harm others.

Utilitarianism seeks to maximize good by minimizing harm to all while egoism seeks to maximize good by keeping the individual happy. In utilitarianism, actions must be judged on the amount of people (or beings) that benefit from the action as opposed to how many the same action may potentially harm. Proponents argue that utilitarianism results in a greater sum of benefit to its harm, based upon outcome and not intention. However, critics of utilitarianism argue that following the interest of the greater good may result in tremendous harm to a large number of individuals.

Meanwhile, egoists argue that acting in self-interest can result in position action because the individual knows best how to benefit his own self, and if everyone were to act in the interest of others, then the general welfare of all would decrease as they are never working for their own good. Egoists trust that others will act in their own interests, thus making it unnecessary to take action solely for their benefit.

Promoted By Zergnet

Advantages and Disadvantages of Ethics; The Difference Between Ethical Egoism & Ethical Subjectivism; ... The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism;

Ethical Principles of Utilitarianism. ... theories or as products of ethical... What Is the Difference Between Teleological ... of Ethical Egoism;

Utilitarianism, also known as consequentialism, ... Deontology is a duty-based moral theory. Deontology states that society needs rules in order to function,...

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism. Ethical Principles of Utilitarianism; Real World & Workplace Examples of Duty-Based Ethics; ...

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism. The major difference between utilitarianism and ethical egoism is where those acts are directed.

Major Differences Between Wood & Coal Burners. ... The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism; ehow.com. About eHow; eHow Blog; How to...

... we can speak of two main teleological moral philosophie: utilitarianism ... What Is the Difference Between ... three major approaches to...

Ethics are moral principles that regulate behavior, including the philosophical study of right and wrong, which is often divided into three parts....

While Utilitarianism was developing in England during the Enlightenment, ... Similarities Between Professional Values & Professional Ethics.

A CEO using utilitarian ethics would think about the consequences for himself, all of his employees, ... The Differences Between Utilitarianism &...

Daniels Fund: Utilitarian Ethics: A Framework for Making Decisions; Santa Clara University: A Framework for Thinking Ethically; ... Difference Between Morals &...

Read the rest here:

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism

Ayn Rand – Ethical Egoism

Posted: at 2:43 am

Ayn Rand - Ethical Egoism

1. Virtue - what the action is to gain and keep value - what one acts to gain & keep.

2. Only one alternative in the universe - to live or not to live.

3. We do not have an instinct to preserve ourselves, only a desire. An instinct would be to know

how to do it.

4. Everything conducive to survival is good - the reverse is evil.

5. Man=s life = the standard of morality

One=s own life is his purpose.

A being who does not hold his own life as the motive and purpose is acting on the standard of death.

6. Help others only as you desire based on selfish pleasure in the value of his person and his

struggle.

James Rachels - Ethical egoism vs. Psychological egoism

Ethical egoism endorses selfishness, not foolishness.

3 arguments in favor of ethical egoism:

1. We are familiar with our own wants and needs

2. We are best fit to pursue them

3. We know desires of others only imperfectly.

4. To be others= keepers would be >bungled.=

5. Looking out for others is intrusive

6. Making others the object of charity is demeaning to them.

NOTE: all of these are non-egoistic reasons. Paradoxical.

Three Arguments against Ethical Egoism:

1. Cannot provide solutions to conflicts of interest.. B and K example.

2. Logically inconsistent. If B and K try to protect themselves, their actions are both wrong and not wrong at the same time.

It does not work because it depends on the notion that "one ought not to prevent another from doing his duty." If we reject this, it is not inconsistent.

3. Egoism is an arbitrary theory - we divide people into types and then say that "I deserve X" and you don't

See the original post here:

Ayn Rand - Ethical Egoism

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ayn Rand – Ethical Egoism

Ethical egoism – RationalWiki

Posted: June 7, 2016 at 7:44 pm

Ethical egoism is the consequentialist philosophy which states that morality should be based on self-interest. It is the philosophical basis for many libertarians and (so they claim) Randroids but also got support from Thomas Hobbes.[1]. Some egoists that do not believe in the existence of ethics call themselves rational egoists, because they want to be selfish, but do not want to support metaphysical ideas like ethics and morals.

Ethical egoism is based on three arguments:

It is the polar opposite of ethical altruism, the belief that one ought to live for others, and is contrasted with utilitarianism, which is objective. Egoism is subjective, meaning that its implications and conclusions change from person to person and nothing is objectively ethical. This is interesting considering that some of the most vocal proponents of ethical egoism are so-called Objectivists.[2]

Egoism is very appealing to some because it philosophically justifies selfishness, even at the expense of others, and therefore reduces feelings of guilt after acting like a heartless jerk. Also, being a jerk is their moral equivalent of being nice and vice versa.

Ethical egoism is seen as arbitrary because it values the selfish individual more than other people and there are no objective grounds for this. Similarly racism values one race more than others arbitrarily.[1]

Contrary to many strawmen arguments, egoism does not mean that you should never act in the interest of another, even if it does not benefit you. Instead, it is acting to benefit yourself, regardless of whether it harms or benefits another. Another way of saying this is that intentions are always selfish. Results may vary, whether they are good for others or not. This is because those who selfishly refuse to help others later find others will not return favours since they received none. If some misfortune arises and the egoist now needs the unselfish help of another, and if everyone is a consistent egoist, the egoist may or may not get the help he needs. So in the interests of self-interest, an egoist must act altruistically, at least sometimes, even if intentions are only about personal gain, thus why it is a relativistic philosophy. There are three types of egoism: universal (everybody should act for their own self-benefit), personal (the egoist is an egoist, but other people can be altruistic or utilitarian), and individual (everybody acts for one individual's self-benefit, which is completely unrealistic).

Alternatively, many egoists are also Individualists, like Stirner and Nietzsche, who would say that those that require the help of other do not deserve the help of others.[3] Incidentally normal people who are not sociopaths would likely lose self respect and become less happy if they only helped others at such times.[citationneeded]

Ethical egoism, like all exclusively subjective philosophies, is prone to constant self-contradiction because it supports all individuals' self interests. It also can lead to conclusions such as choosing not to intervene in a crime against another. Egoists have difficulty caring about anything that does not deal with themselves, which is one reason why ethical egoism is so impractical for people who are very aware of the world. The very legitimacy of the theory is often called into question because it prevents its own adherents from taking reasonable stances on major political and social issues and cannot in itself solve these issues, without resorting to popular choice.[3]

See the original post:

Ethical egoism - RationalWiki

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ethical egoism – RationalWiki

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism

Posted: at 7:44 pm

Follow

Consequentialism is a moral theory that states that the consequences of one's actions are the basis for any morality or judgment toward that action. Both utilitarianism and ethical egoism are theories within consequentialism that focus on the outcome of conduct as the primary motivation of that action and any critique of whether or not that conduct is ethical. The major difference between utilitarianism and ethical egoism is where those acts are directed.

Utilitarianism focuses on the idea of the greater good. Essentially, this ethical theory intends to maximize good for the the most people. The moral worth of any action is judged by how much good results for all sentient beings. While some individuals may suffer from these actions, utilitarianism holds that the conduct may still be ethical if it does more good for a greater number of people than it harms.

Ethical egoism, also known simply as egoism, holds that moral conduct ought to be judged through self-interest. Egoism states that the good consequences for the individual agent outweigh the consequences placed upon others. In egoism, actions could be considered ethical for the individual if the one taking the action is benefited, while any benefit or detriment to the welfare of others is a side effect and not as important as the consequences for the individual.

The primary differences between these two theories, keeping in mind that there are numerous sub-theories within each branch of thought, is the value placed between the individual and others. In utilitarianism, the most ethical action may be that which harms the individual agent but maximizes the positive impact for the most people overall, essentially placing the emphasis on the whole as opposed to the individual. In egoism, the individual has a greater value than others, thus it is ethical to act in one's own self-interest even if it may potentially harm others.

Utilitarianism seeks to maximize good by minimizing harm to all while egoism seeks to maximize good by keeping the individual happy. In utilitarianism, actions must be judged on the amount of people (or beings) that benefit from the action as opposed to how many the same action may potentially harm. Proponents argue that utilitarianism results in a greater sum of benefit to its harm, based upon outcome and not intention. However, critics of utilitarianism argue that following the interest of the greater good may result in tremendous harm to a large number of individuals.

Meanwhile, egoists argue that acting in self-interest can result in position action because the individual knows best how to benefit his own self, and if everyone were to act in the interest of others, then the general welfare of all would decrease as they are never working for their own good. Egoists trust that others will act in their own interests, thus making it unnecessary to take action solely for their benefit.

Promoted By Zergnet

Advantages and Disadvantages of Ethics; The Difference Between Ethical Egoism & Ethical Subjectivism; ... The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism;

Ethical Principles of Utilitarianism. ... theories or as products of ethical... What Is the Difference Between Teleological ... of Ethical Egoism;

Utilitarianism, also known as consequentialism, ... Deontology is a duty-based moral theory. Deontology states that society needs rules in order to function,...

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism. Ethical Principles of Utilitarianism; Real World & Workplace Examples of Duty-Based Ethics; ...

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism. The major difference between utilitarianism and ethical egoism is where those acts are directed.

Major Differences Between Wood & Coal Burners. ... The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism; ehow.com. About eHow; eHow Blog; How to...

... we can speak of two main teleological moral philosophie: utilitarianism ... What Is the Difference Between ... three major approaches to...

Ethics are moral principles that regulate behavior, including the philosophical study of right and wrong, which is often divided into three parts....

While Utilitarianism was developing in England during the Enlightenment, ... Similarities Between Professional Values & Professional Ethics.

A CEO using utilitarian ethics would think about the consequences for himself, all of his employees, ... The Differences Between Utilitarianism &...

Daniels Fund: Utilitarian Ethics: A Framework for Making Decisions; Santa Clara University: A Framework for Thinking Ethically; ... Difference Between Morals &...

See the rest here:

The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on The Differences Between Utilitarianism & Ethical Egoism

Ethical Egoism – Lander University

Posted: March 23, 2016 at 10:44 pm

Abstract: The various forms of ethical egoism are defined. Standard objections to ethical egoism are evaluated, and the conclusion is drawn that ethical egoism is incomplete.

I. Ethical egoism is the prescriptive doctrine that all persons ought to act from their own self-interest.

A theory of ethics should

Therefore, the theory should be both consistent and complete.

e.g., the injunctions from folklore morals, "Haste makes waste" and "Look before you leap" would be inconsistent with "A stitch in time saves nine," or "The race is to the swift."

e.g., In Christian ethics, the principle "Render therefore unto Caesar the things which are Caesar's" (Matthew 22:21) is meant to distinguish between secular and religious situations in order to avoid political difficulty for religious belief and so would be an incomplete theory of action in the secular realm.

Consequently, the three ways to raise objections to an ethical theory is to show that the theory is

I. Charge: Ethical egoism is contradictory because it allows one and the same act to be evaluated as both right and wrong. Charge: the theory is mistaken in truth; it is inconsistent.

Therefore, praising Jack's qualities is both right and wrongright for Jack and wrong for Jill.

II. Charge: Ethical egoism is committed to giving inconsistent advice. (The charge is inconsistency.)

III. Charge: If the (universal) egoist believes that each person should promote his own interest, then isn't he acting against his own interest to state his theory. (The charge is inconsistency.)

IV. Charge: There are certain interpersonal decisions that have to be made that transcend the egoist's point of view. (The charge is of incompleteness)

V. Final Comments on Ethical Egoism: the egoist is often seen to be egotistical and selfish, rather someone acting under enlightened self-interest.

E.g., An ethical egoist can act in self-interest by contributing to the Salvation Army or to the United Fund.

VI. If the egoist is to choose what is in his own interest, then he must have the personal freedom to choose.

Recommended Sources

Solipsism: An excellent discussion of the role of solipsism in the history of Western and Eastern philosophy and its role as a limiting case in thought experiments and epistemology from Wikipedia. See also from this source links to various related concepts to egoism including ethical egoism.

Ethical Egoism: A section of the entry "Egoism" discussing arguments for and against by Robert Shaver published in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Ethical Egoism: A section of the entry "Egoism' from the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy by Alexander Moseley emphasizing conflict resolution.

Read this article:

Ethical Egoism - Lander University

Posted in Ethical Egoism | Comments Off on Ethical Egoism – Lander University

Page 9«..78910